Why is Voevodsky's motivic homotopy theory 'the right' approach?











up vote
22
down vote

favorite
9












Morel and Voevoedsky developed what is now called motivic homotopy theory, which aims to apply techniques of algebraic topology to algebraic varieties and, more generally, to schemes. A simple way of stating the idea is that we wish to find a model structure on some algebraic category related to that of varieties or that of schemes, so as to apply homotopy theory in an abstract sense.



The uninitiated will find the name of the theory intriguing, and will perceive the simple idea presented above as a very fair approach, but upon reading the details of the theory, he might get somewhat puzzled, if not worried, about some of its aspects. We begin with the following aspects, which are added for completeness.




  • The relevant category we start out with is not a category of schemes, but a much larger category of simplicial sheaves over the category of smooth schemes endowed with a suitable Grothendieck topology. A relevant MathOverflow topic is here.


  • The choice of Grothendieck topology is the Nisnevich topology, the reasons being discussed right over here.


  • The choice of smooth schemes rather than arbitrary schemes has been discussed here.



Let us now suppose the uninitiated has accepted the technical reasons that are mentioned inside the linked pages, and that he will henceforth ignore whatever aesthetic shortcomings he may still perceive. He continues reading through the introduction, but soon finds himself facing two more aspects which worries him even more.




  • The resulting homotopy theory does not behave as our rough intuition would like. In particular, what we might reasonable want to hold, such as the fact that a space ought to be homotopy equivalent to the product of itself with the affine line, is false. We solve the issue by simply forcing them to be homotopy equivalent, and hope that whatever theory rolls out is more satisfactory.


  • There are two intuitive analogues of spheres in algebraic geometry, and the theory does not manage to identify them. We solve the issue by just leaving both of them into the game, accepting that all homology and cohomology theories will be bigraded, and we hope that this doesn't cause issues.



The fact that the resulting theory is satisfactory, has proved itself over time. But hopefully the reader will not find it unreasonable that the uninitiated perceives the two issues mentioned above as a warning sign that the approach is on the wrong track, if not the 'wrong' one altogether; moreover, he will perceive the solutions presented as 'naive', as though it were but a symptomatic treatment of aforementioned warning signs.




Question. How would you convince the uninitiated that Voevodsky's approach of motivic homotopy theory is 'the right one'?











share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.
















  • 2




    Someone here told me a few months back that there is some kind of attempt to do $mathbf{P}^1$ homotopy theory, where algebraic K-theory might be actually homotopy invariant (it isn't $mathbf{A}^1$ invariant). It's a vague comment but maybe someone else here can flesh it out. This seems to me to indicate that there's at least some way in which the motivic category isn't optimal.
    – Harry Gindi
    14 hours ago








  • 14




    This is a good question, but please consider changing your user image
    – leibnewtz
    14 hours ago






  • 3




    I'm glad you changed the image. But some symbols are simply unacceptable to use even once, and I for one will never answer any of your questions.
    – Noah Snyder
    11 hours ago






  • 3




    The mysterious comments here led me to ask a meta question, which I hope is not innapropriate: meta.mathoverflow.net/questions/3981/…
    – Samantha Y
    10 hours ago












  • I don't understand exactly the complaints, but the point is that one wants motives to have the properties shared by all the main known realisations (for instance, perverse sheaves). So a contractible line, a (co)homological nature (coming from spectra after the stabilisation), a bigrading (due to the Tate twists which are always present in the known (co)homologies) are all desirable features. The restriction to Nisnevich descent comes from its good behaviour in K-theory (motivic complexes were first conceived through K-theory by Beilinson and Lichtenbaum)...
    – user40276
    5 hours ago















up vote
22
down vote

favorite
9












Morel and Voevoedsky developed what is now called motivic homotopy theory, which aims to apply techniques of algebraic topology to algebraic varieties and, more generally, to schemes. A simple way of stating the idea is that we wish to find a model structure on some algebraic category related to that of varieties or that of schemes, so as to apply homotopy theory in an abstract sense.



The uninitiated will find the name of the theory intriguing, and will perceive the simple idea presented above as a very fair approach, but upon reading the details of the theory, he might get somewhat puzzled, if not worried, about some of its aspects. We begin with the following aspects, which are added for completeness.




  • The relevant category we start out with is not a category of schemes, but a much larger category of simplicial sheaves over the category of smooth schemes endowed with a suitable Grothendieck topology. A relevant MathOverflow topic is here.


  • The choice of Grothendieck topology is the Nisnevich topology, the reasons being discussed right over here.


  • The choice of smooth schemes rather than arbitrary schemes has been discussed here.



Let us now suppose the uninitiated has accepted the technical reasons that are mentioned inside the linked pages, and that he will henceforth ignore whatever aesthetic shortcomings he may still perceive. He continues reading through the introduction, but soon finds himself facing two more aspects which worries him even more.




  • The resulting homotopy theory does not behave as our rough intuition would like. In particular, what we might reasonable want to hold, such as the fact that a space ought to be homotopy equivalent to the product of itself with the affine line, is false. We solve the issue by simply forcing them to be homotopy equivalent, and hope that whatever theory rolls out is more satisfactory.


  • There are two intuitive analogues of spheres in algebraic geometry, and the theory does not manage to identify them. We solve the issue by just leaving both of them into the game, accepting that all homology and cohomology theories will be bigraded, and we hope that this doesn't cause issues.



The fact that the resulting theory is satisfactory, has proved itself over time. But hopefully the reader will not find it unreasonable that the uninitiated perceives the two issues mentioned above as a warning sign that the approach is on the wrong track, if not the 'wrong' one altogether; moreover, he will perceive the solutions presented as 'naive', as though it were but a symptomatic treatment of aforementioned warning signs.




Question. How would you convince the uninitiated that Voevodsky's approach of motivic homotopy theory is 'the right one'?











share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.
















  • 2




    Someone here told me a few months back that there is some kind of attempt to do $mathbf{P}^1$ homotopy theory, where algebraic K-theory might be actually homotopy invariant (it isn't $mathbf{A}^1$ invariant). It's a vague comment but maybe someone else here can flesh it out. This seems to me to indicate that there's at least some way in which the motivic category isn't optimal.
    – Harry Gindi
    14 hours ago








  • 14




    This is a good question, but please consider changing your user image
    – leibnewtz
    14 hours ago






  • 3




    I'm glad you changed the image. But some symbols are simply unacceptable to use even once, and I for one will never answer any of your questions.
    – Noah Snyder
    11 hours ago






  • 3




    The mysterious comments here led me to ask a meta question, which I hope is not innapropriate: meta.mathoverflow.net/questions/3981/…
    – Samantha Y
    10 hours ago












  • I don't understand exactly the complaints, but the point is that one wants motives to have the properties shared by all the main known realisations (for instance, perverse sheaves). So a contractible line, a (co)homological nature (coming from spectra after the stabilisation), a bigrading (due to the Tate twists which are always present in the known (co)homologies) are all desirable features. The restriction to Nisnevich descent comes from its good behaviour in K-theory (motivic complexes were first conceived through K-theory by Beilinson and Lichtenbaum)...
    – user40276
    5 hours ago













up vote
22
down vote

favorite
9









up vote
22
down vote

favorite
9






9





Morel and Voevoedsky developed what is now called motivic homotopy theory, which aims to apply techniques of algebraic topology to algebraic varieties and, more generally, to schemes. A simple way of stating the idea is that we wish to find a model structure on some algebraic category related to that of varieties or that of schemes, so as to apply homotopy theory in an abstract sense.



The uninitiated will find the name of the theory intriguing, and will perceive the simple idea presented above as a very fair approach, but upon reading the details of the theory, he might get somewhat puzzled, if not worried, about some of its aspects. We begin with the following aspects, which are added for completeness.




  • The relevant category we start out with is not a category of schemes, but a much larger category of simplicial sheaves over the category of smooth schemes endowed with a suitable Grothendieck topology. A relevant MathOverflow topic is here.


  • The choice of Grothendieck topology is the Nisnevich topology, the reasons being discussed right over here.


  • The choice of smooth schemes rather than arbitrary schemes has been discussed here.



Let us now suppose the uninitiated has accepted the technical reasons that are mentioned inside the linked pages, and that he will henceforth ignore whatever aesthetic shortcomings he may still perceive. He continues reading through the introduction, but soon finds himself facing two more aspects which worries him even more.




  • The resulting homotopy theory does not behave as our rough intuition would like. In particular, what we might reasonable want to hold, such as the fact that a space ought to be homotopy equivalent to the product of itself with the affine line, is false. We solve the issue by simply forcing them to be homotopy equivalent, and hope that whatever theory rolls out is more satisfactory.


  • There are two intuitive analogues of spheres in algebraic geometry, and the theory does not manage to identify them. We solve the issue by just leaving both of them into the game, accepting that all homology and cohomology theories will be bigraded, and we hope that this doesn't cause issues.



The fact that the resulting theory is satisfactory, has proved itself over time. But hopefully the reader will not find it unreasonable that the uninitiated perceives the two issues mentioned above as a warning sign that the approach is on the wrong track, if not the 'wrong' one altogether; moreover, he will perceive the solutions presented as 'naive', as though it were but a symptomatic treatment of aforementioned warning signs.




Question. How would you convince the uninitiated that Voevodsky's approach of motivic homotopy theory is 'the right one'?











share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











Morel and Voevoedsky developed what is now called motivic homotopy theory, which aims to apply techniques of algebraic topology to algebraic varieties and, more generally, to schemes. A simple way of stating the idea is that we wish to find a model structure on some algebraic category related to that of varieties or that of schemes, so as to apply homotopy theory in an abstract sense.



The uninitiated will find the name of the theory intriguing, and will perceive the simple idea presented above as a very fair approach, but upon reading the details of the theory, he might get somewhat puzzled, if not worried, about some of its aspects. We begin with the following aspects, which are added for completeness.




  • The relevant category we start out with is not a category of schemes, but a much larger category of simplicial sheaves over the category of smooth schemes endowed with a suitable Grothendieck topology. A relevant MathOverflow topic is here.


  • The choice of Grothendieck topology is the Nisnevich topology, the reasons being discussed right over here.


  • The choice of smooth schemes rather than arbitrary schemes has been discussed here.



Let us now suppose the uninitiated has accepted the technical reasons that are mentioned inside the linked pages, and that he will henceforth ignore whatever aesthetic shortcomings he may still perceive. He continues reading through the introduction, but soon finds himself facing two more aspects which worries him even more.




  • The resulting homotopy theory does not behave as our rough intuition would like. In particular, what we might reasonable want to hold, such as the fact that a space ought to be homotopy equivalent to the product of itself with the affine line, is false. We solve the issue by simply forcing them to be homotopy equivalent, and hope that whatever theory rolls out is more satisfactory.


  • There are two intuitive analogues of spheres in algebraic geometry, and the theory does not manage to identify them. We solve the issue by just leaving both of them into the game, accepting that all homology and cohomology theories will be bigraded, and we hope that this doesn't cause issues.



The fact that the resulting theory is satisfactory, has proved itself over time. But hopefully the reader will not find it unreasonable that the uninitiated perceives the two issues mentioned above as a warning sign that the approach is on the wrong track, if not the 'wrong' one altogether; moreover, he will perceive the solutions presented as 'naive', as though it were but a symptomatic treatment of aforementioned warning signs.




Question. How would you convince the uninitiated that Voevodsky's approach of motivic homotopy theory is 'the right one'?








ag.algebraic-geometry at.algebraic-topology homotopy-theory model-categories motivic-homotopy






share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question






New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









asked 15 hours ago









Patriot

1203




1203




New contributor




Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






Patriot is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








  • 2




    Someone here told me a few months back that there is some kind of attempt to do $mathbf{P}^1$ homotopy theory, where algebraic K-theory might be actually homotopy invariant (it isn't $mathbf{A}^1$ invariant). It's a vague comment but maybe someone else here can flesh it out. This seems to me to indicate that there's at least some way in which the motivic category isn't optimal.
    – Harry Gindi
    14 hours ago








  • 14




    This is a good question, but please consider changing your user image
    – leibnewtz
    14 hours ago






  • 3




    I'm glad you changed the image. But some symbols are simply unacceptable to use even once, and I for one will never answer any of your questions.
    – Noah Snyder
    11 hours ago






  • 3




    The mysterious comments here led me to ask a meta question, which I hope is not innapropriate: meta.mathoverflow.net/questions/3981/…
    – Samantha Y
    10 hours ago












  • I don't understand exactly the complaints, but the point is that one wants motives to have the properties shared by all the main known realisations (for instance, perverse sheaves). So a contractible line, a (co)homological nature (coming from spectra after the stabilisation), a bigrading (due to the Tate twists which are always present in the known (co)homologies) are all desirable features. The restriction to Nisnevich descent comes from its good behaviour in K-theory (motivic complexes were first conceived through K-theory by Beilinson and Lichtenbaum)...
    – user40276
    5 hours ago














  • 2




    Someone here told me a few months back that there is some kind of attempt to do $mathbf{P}^1$ homotopy theory, where algebraic K-theory might be actually homotopy invariant (it isn't $mathbf{A}^1$ invariant). It's a vague comment but maybe someone else here can flesh it out. This seems to me to indicate that there's at least some way in which the motivic category isn't optimal.
    – Harry Gindi
    14 hours ago








  • 14




    This is a good question, but please consider changing your user image
    – leibnewtz
    14 hours ago






  • 3




    I'm glad you changed the image. But some symbols are simply unacceptable to use even once, and I for one will never answer any of your questions.
    – Noah Snyder
    11 hours ago






  • 3




    The mysterious comments here led me to ask a meta question, which I hope is not innapropriate: meta.mathoverflow.net/questions/3981/…
    – Samantha Y
    10 hours ago












  • I don't understand exactly the complaints, but the point is that one wants motives to have the properties shared by all the main known realisations (for instance, perverse sheaves). So a contractible line, a (co)homological nature (coming from spectra after the stabilisation), a bigrading (due to the Tate twists which are always present in the known (co)homologies) are all desirable features. The restriction to Nisnevich descent comes from its good behaviour in K-theory (motivic complexes were first conceived through K-theory by Beilinson and Lichtenbaum)...
    – user40276
    5 hours ago








2




2




Someone here told me a few months back that there is some kind of attempt to do $mathbf{P}^1$ homotopy theory, where algebraic K-theory might be actually homotopy invariant (it isn't $mathbf{A}^1$ invariant). It's a vague comment but maybe someone else here can flesh it out. This seems to me to indicate that there's at least some way in which the motivic category isn't optimal.
– Harry Gindi
14 hours ago






Someone here told me a few months back that there is some kind of attempt to do $mathbf{P}^1$ homotopy theory, where algebraic K-theory might be actually homotopy invariant (it isn't $mathbf{A}^1$ invariant). It's a vague comment but maybe someone else here can flesh it out. This seems to me to indicate that there's at least some way in which the motivic category isn't optimal.
– Harry Gindi
14 hours ago






14




14




This is a good question, but please consider changing your user image
– leibnewtz
14 hours ago




This is a good question, but please consider changing your user image
– leibnewtz
14 hours ago




3




3




I'm glad you changed the image. But some symbols are simply unacceptable to use even once, and I for one will never answer any of your questions.
– Noah Snyder
11 hours ago




I'm glad you changed the image. But some symbols are simply unacceptable to use even once, and I for one will never answer any of your questions.
– Noah Snyder
11 hours ago




3




3




The mysterious comments here led me to ask a meta question, which I hope is not innapropriate: meta.mathoverflow.net/questions/3981/…
– Samantha Y
10 hours ago






The mysterious comments here led me to ask a meta question, which I hope is not innapropriate: meta.mathoverflow.net/questions/3981/…
– Samantha Y
10 hours ago














I don't understand exactly the complaints, but the point is that one wants motives to have the properties shared by all the main known realisations (for instance, perverse sheaves). So a contractible line, a (co)homological nature (coming from spectra after the stabilisation), a bigrading (due to the Tate twists which are always present in the known (co)homologies) are all desirable features. The restriction to Nisnevich descent comes from its good behaviour in K-theory (motivic complexes were first conceived through K-theory by Beilinson and Lichtenbaum)...
– user40276
5 hours ago




I don't understand exactly the complaints, but the point is that one wants motives to have the properties shared by all the main known realisations (for instance, perverse sheaves). So a contractible line, a (co)homological nature (coming from spectra after the stabilisation), a bigrading (due to the Tate twists which are always present in the known (co)homologies) are all desirable features. The restriction to Nisnevich descent comes from its good behaviour in K-theory (motivic complexes were first conceived through K-theory by Beilinson and Lichtenbaum)...
– user40276
5 hours ago










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
13
down vote













(Don't be afraid about the word "$infty$-category" here: they're just a convenient framework to do homotopy theory in).





I'm going to try with a very naive answer, although I'm not sure I understand your question exactly.



The (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has a universal property. To be precise the following statements are true




Theorem: Every functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a(n $infty$-)category $C$ that




  • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant (i.e. for which $E(Xtimes mathbb{A}^1)to E(X)$ is an equivalence)

  • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology" (i.e. sends elementary Nisnevich squares to pushout squares)


factors uniquely through the unstable motivic ($infty$-)category.




(see Dugger Universal Homotopy Theories, section 8)




Theorem: Every symmetric monoidal functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a pointed presentable symmetric monoidal ($infty$-)category that




  • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant

  • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology"

  • sends the "Tate motive" (i.e. the summand of $E(mathbb{P}^1)$ obtained by splitting off the summand corresponding to $E(mathrm{Spec}S)to E(mathbb{P}^1)$) to an invertible object


factors uniquely through the stable motivic ($infty$-)category.




(see Robalo K-Theory and the bridge to noncommutative motives, corollary 2.39)



These two theorems are saying that any two functors that "behave like a homology theory on smooth $S$-schemes" will factor uniquely through the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category. Examples are $l$-adic étale cohomology, algebraic K-theory (if $S$ is regular Noetherian), motivic cohomology (as given by Bloch's higher Chow groups)... Conversely, the canonical functor from $mathrm{Sm}_S$ to the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has these properties. So the (un)stable motivic homotopy theory is in this precise sense the home of the universal homology theory. In particular all the properties we can prove for $mathcal{H}(S)$ or $SH(S)$ reflect on every homology theory satisfying the above properties (purity being the obvious example).





Let me say a couple of words about the two aspects that "worry you"




  • $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance needs to be imposed. That's not surprising: we do need to do that also for topological spaces, when we quotient the maps by homotopy equivalence (or, more precisely, we need to replace the set of maps by a space of maps, where paths are given by homotopies: this more complicated procedure is also responsible for the usage of simplicial presheaves rather than just ordinary presheaves)


  • Having more kinds of spheres is actually quite common in homotopy theory. A good test case for this is $C_2$-equivariant homotopy theory. See for example this answer of mine for a more detailed exploration of the analogy.





Surprisingly, possibly the most problematic of the three defining properties of $SH(S)$ is the $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance. In fact there are several "homology theories" we'd like to study that do not satisfy it (e.g. crystalline cohomology). I know some people are trying to find a replacement for $SH(S)$ where these theories might live. As far as I know there are some definitions of such replacements but I don't think they have been shown to have properties comparable to the very interesting structure you can find on $SH(S)$, so I don't know whether this will bear fruit or not in the future.






share|cite|improve this answer






























    up vote
    12
    down vote













    I just want to point out, with regards to your second question, that the fact that the $mathbb P^1$ is not equivalent to a simplicial complex homotopic to the sphere built out of affine spaces (or whichever model for an un-Tate-twisted sphere) is exactly what you would expect from Grothendieck et. al.'s theory of motives.



    In fact having a homology or cohomology theory without a notion of Tate twist would be very strong evidence that we are on the wrong track!



    More carefully one might point out that we want a map to etale cohomology and a notion of Chern class, which requires the Tate twisting because Tate twists show up in the Chern class map in etale cohomology.






    share|cite|improve this answer

















    • 1




      Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
      – Denis Nardin
      5 hours ago











    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "504"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });






    Patriot is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f315816%2fwhy-is-voevodskys-motivic-homotopy-theory-the-right-approach%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    13
    down vote













    (Don't be afraid about the word "$infty$-category" here: they're just a convenient framework to do homotopy theory in).





    I'm going to try with a very naive answer, although I'm not sure I understand your question exactly.



    The (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has a universal property. To be precise the following statements are true




    Theorem: Every functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a(n $infty$-)category $C$ that




    • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant (i.e. for which $E(Xtimes mathbb{A}^1)to E(X)$ is an equivalence)

    • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology" (i.e. sends elementary Nisnevich squares to pushout squares)


    factors uniquely through the unstable motivic ($infty$-)category.




    (see Dugger Universal Homotopy Theories, section 8)




    Theorem: Every symmetric monoidal functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a pointed presentable symmetric monoidal ($infty$-)category that




    • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant

    • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology"

    • sends the "Tate motive" (i.e. the summand of $E(mathbb{P}^1)$ obtained by splitting off the summand corresponding to $E(mathrm{Spec}S)to E(mathbb{P}^1)$) to an invertible object


    factors uniquely through the stable motivic ($infty$-)category.




    (see Robalo K-Theory and the bridge to noncommutative motives, corollary 2.39)



    These two theorems are saying that any two functors that "behave like a homology theory on smooth $S$-schemes" will factor uniquely through the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category. Examples are $l$-adic étale cohomology, algebraic K-theory (if $S$ is regular Noetherian), motivic cohomology (as given by Bloch's higher Chow groups)... Conversely, the canonical functor from $mathrm{Sm}_S$ to the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has these properties. So the (un)stable motivic homotopy theory is in this precise sense the home of the universal homology theory. In particular all the properties we can prove for $mathcal{H}(S)$ or $SH(S)$ reflect on every homology theory satisfying the above properties (purity being the obvious example).





    Let me say a couple of words about the two aspects that "worry you"




    • $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance needs to be imposed. That's not surprising: we do need to do that also for topological spaces, when we quotient the maps by homotopy equivalence (or, more precisely, we need to replace the set of maps by a space of maps, where paths are given by homotopies: this more complicated procedure is also responsible for the usage of simplicial presheaves rather than just ordinary presheaves)


    • Having more kinds of spheres is actually quite common in homotopy theory. A good test case for this is $C_2$-equivariant homotopy theory. See for example this answer of mine for a more detailed exploration of the analogy.





    Surprisingly, possibly the most problematic of the three defining properties of $SH(S)$ is the $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance. In fact there are several "homology theories" we'd like to study that do not satisfy it (e.g. crystalline cohomology). I know some people are trying to find a replacement for $SH(S)$ where these theories might live. As far as I know there are some definitions of such replacements but I don't think they have been shown to have properties comparable to the very interesting structure you can find on $SH(S)$, so I don't know whether this will bear fruit or not in the future.






    share|cite|improve this answer



























      up vote
      13
      down vote













      (Don't be afraid about the word "$infty$-category" here: they're just a convenient framework to do homotopy theory in).





      I'm going to try with a very naive answer, although I'm not sure I understand your question exactly.



      The (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has a universal property. To be precise the following statements are true




      Theorem: Every functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a(n $infty$-)category $C$ that




      • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant (i.e. for which $E(Xtimes mathbb{A}^1)to E(X)$ is an equivalence)

      • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology" (i.e. sends elementary Nisnevich squares to pushout squares)


      factors uniquely through the unstable motivic ($infty$-)category.




      (see Dugger Universal Homotopy Theories, section 8)




      Theorem: Every symmetric monoidal functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a pointed presentable symmetric monoidal ($infty$-)category that




      • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant

      • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology"

      • sends the "Tate motive" (i.e. the summand of $E(mathbb{P}^1)$ obtained by splitting off the summand corresponding to $E(mathrm{Spec}S)to E(mathbb{P}^1)$) to an invertible object


      factors uniquely through the stable motivic ($infty$-)category.




      (see Robalo K-Theory and the bridge to noncommutative motives, corollary 2.39)



      These two theorems are saying that any two functors that "behave like a homology theory on smooth $S$-schemes" will factor uniquely through the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category. Examples are $l$-adic étale cohomology, algebraic K-theory (if $S$ is regular Noetherian), motivic cohomology (as given by Bloch's higher Chow groups)... Conversely, the canonical functor from $mathrm{Sm}_S$ to the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has these properties. So the (un)stable motivic homotopy theory is in this precise sense the home of the universal homology theory. In particular all the properties we can prove for $mathcal{H}(S)$ or $SH(S)$ reflect on every homology theory satisfying the above properties (purity being the obvious example).





      Let me say a couple of words about the two aspects that "worry you"




      • $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance needs to be imposed. That's not surprising: we do need to do that also for topological spaces, when we quotient the maps by homotopy equivalence (or, more precisely, we need to replace the set of maps by a space of maps, where paths are given by homotopies: this more complicated procedure is also responsible for the usage of simplicial presheaves rather than just ordinary presheaves)


      • Having more kinds of spheres is actually quite common in homotopy theory. A good test case for this is $C_2$-equivariant homotopy theory. See for example this answer of mine for a more detailed exploration of the analogy.





      Surprisingly, possibly the most problematic of the three defining properties of $SH(S)$ is the $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance. In fact there are several "homology theories" we'd like to study that do not satisfy it (e.g. crystalline cohomology). I know some people are trying to find a replacement for $SH(S)$ where these theories might live. As far as I know there are some definitions of such replacements but I don't think they have been shown to have properties comparable to the very interesting structure you can find on $SH(S)$, so I don't know whether this will bear fruit or not in the future.






      share|cite|improve this answer

























        up vote
        13
        down vote










        up vote
        13
        down vote









        (Don't be afraid about the word "$infty$-category" here: they're just a convenient framework to do homotopy theory in).





        I'm going to try with a very naive answer, although I'm not sure I understand your question exactly.



        The (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has a universal property. To be precise the following statements are true




        Theorem: Every functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a(n $infty$-)category $C$ that




        • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant (i.e. for which $E(Xtimes mathbb{A}^1)to E(X)$ is an equivalence)

        • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology" (i.e. sends elementary Nisnevich squares to pushout squares)


        factors uniquely through the unstable motivic ($infty$-)category.




        (see Dugger Universal Homotopy Theories, section 8)




        Theorem: Every symmetric monoidal functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a pointed presentable symmetric monoidal ($infty$-)category that




        • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant

        • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology"

        • sends the "Tate motive" (i.e. the summand of $E(mathbb{P}^1)$ obtained by splitting off the summand corresponding to $E(mathrm{Spec}S)to E(mathbb{P}^1)$) to an invertible object


        factors uniquely through the stable motivic ($infty$-)category.




        (see Robalo K-Theory and the bridge to noncommutative motives, corollary 2.39)



        These two theorems are saying that any two functors that "behave like a homology theory on smooth $S$-schemes" will factor uniquely through the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category. Examples are $l$-adic étale cohomology, algebraic K-theory (if $S$ is regular Noetherian), motivic cohomology (as given by Bloch's higher Chow groups)... Conversely, the canonical functor from $mathrm{Sm}_S$ to the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has these properties. So the (un)stable motivic homotopy theory is in this precise sense the home of the universal homology theory. In particular all the properties we can prove for $mathcal{H}(S)$ or $SH(S)$ reflect on every homology theory satisfying the above properties (purity being the obvious example).





        Let me say a couple of words about the two aspects that "worry you"




        • $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance needs to be imposed. That's not surprising: we do need to do that also for topological spaces, when we quotient the maps by homotopy equivalence (or, more precisely, we need to replace the set of maps by a space of maps, where paths are given by homotopies: this more complicated procedure is also responsible for the usage of simplicial presheaves rather than just ordinary presheaves)


        • Having more kinds of spheres is actually quite common in homotopy theory. A good test case for this is $C_2$-equivariant homotopy theory. See for example this answer of mine for a more detailed exploration of the analogy.





        Surprisingly, possibly the most problematic of the three defining properties of $SH(S)$ is the $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance. In fact there are several "homology theories" we'd like to study that do not satisfy it (e.g. crystalline cohomology). I know some people are trying to find a replacement for $SH(S)$ where these theories might live. As far as I know there are some definitions of such replacements but I don't think they have been shown to have properties comparable to the very interesting structure you can find on $SH(S)$, so I don't know whether this will bear fruit or not in the future.






        share|cite|improve this answer














        (Don't be afraid about the word "$infty$-category" here: they're just a convenient framework to do homotopy theory in).





        I'm going to try with a very naive answer, although I'm not sure I understand your question exactly.



        The (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has a universal property. To be precise the following statements are true




        Theorem: Every functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a(n $infty$-)category $C$ that




        • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant (i.e. for which $E(Xtimes mathbb{A}^1)to E(X)$ is an equivalence)

        • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology" (i.e. sends elementary Nisnevich squares to pushout squares)


        factors uniquely through the unstable motivic ($infty$-)category.




        (see Dugger Universal Homotopy Theories, section 8)




        Theorem: Every symmetric monoidal functor $E:mathrm{Sm}_Sto C$ to a pointed presentable symmetric monoidal ($infty$-)category that




        • is $mathbb{A}^1$-invariant

        • satisfies "Mayer-Vietoris for the Nisnevich topology"

        • sends the "Tate motive" (i.e. the summand of $E(mathbb{P}^1)$ obtained by splitting off the summand corresponding to $E(mathrm{Spec}S)to E(mathbb{P}^1)$) to an invertible object


        factors uniquely through the stable motivic ($infty$-)category.




        (see Robalo K-Theory and the bridge to noncommutative motives, corollary 2.39)



        These two theorems are saying that any two functors that "behave like a homology theory on smooth $S$-schemes" will factor uniquely through the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category. Examples are $l$-adic étale cohomology, algebraic K-theory (if $S$ is regular Noetherian), motivic cohomology (as given by Bloch's higher Chow groups)... Conversely, the canonical functor from $mathrm{Sm}_S$ to the (un)stable motivic ($infty$-)category has these properties. So the (un)stable motivic homotopy theory is in this precise sense the home of the universal homology theory. In particular all the properties we can prove for $mathcal{H}(S)$ or $SH(S)$ reflect on every homology theory satisfying the above properties (purity being the obvious example).





        Let me say a couple of words about the two aspects that "worry you"




        • $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance needs to be imposed. That's not surprising: we do need to do that also for topological spaces, when we quotient the maps by homotopy equivalence (or, more precisely, we need to replace the set of maps by a space of maps, where paths are given by homotopies: this more complicated procedure is also responsible for the usage of simplicial presheaves rather than just ordinary presheaves)


        • Having more kinds of spheres is actually quite common in homotopy theory. A good test case for this is $C_2$-equivariant homotopy theory. See for example this answer of mine for a more detailed exploration of the analogy.





        Surprisingly, possibly the most problematic of the three defining properties of $SH(S)$ is the $mathbb{A}^1$-invariance. In fact there are several "homology theories" we'd like to study that do not satisfy it (e.g. crystalline cohomology). I know some people are trying to find a replacement for $SH(S)$ where these theories might live. As far as I know there are some definitions of such replacements but I don't think they have been shown to have properties comparable to the very interesting structure you can find on $SH(S)$, so I don't know whether this will bear fruit or not in the future.







        share|cite|improve this answer














        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited 6 hours ago

























        answered 14 hours ago









        Denis Nardin

        7,23512654




        7,23512654






















            up vote
            12
            down vote













            I just want to point out, with regards to your second question, that the fact that the $mathbb P^1$ is not equivalent to a simplicial complex homotopic to the sphere built out of affine spaces (or whichever model for an un-Tate-twisted sphere) is exactly what you would expect from Grothendieck et. al.'s theory of motives.



            In fact having a homology or cohomology theory without a notion of Tate twist would be very strong evidence that we are on the wrong track!



            More carefully one might point out that we want a map to etale cohomology and a notion of Chern class, which requires the Tate twisting because Tate twists show up in the Chern class map in etale cohomology.






            share|cite|improve this answer

















            • 1




              Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
              – Denis Nardin
              5 hours ago















            up vote
            12
            down vote













            I just want to point out, with regards to your second question, that the fact that the $mathbb P^1$ is not equivalent to a simplicial complex homotopic to the sphere built out of affine spaces (or whichever model for an un-Tate-twisted sphere) is exactly what you would expect from Grothendieck et. al.'s theory of motives.



            In fact having a homology or cohomology theory without a notion of Tate twist would be very strong evidence that we are on the wrong track!



            More carefully one might point out that we want a map to etale cohomology and a notion of Chern class, which requires the Tate twisting because Tate twists show up in the Chern class map in etale cohomology.






            share|cite|improve this answer

















            • 1




              Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
              – Denis Nardin
              5 hours ago













            up vote
            12
            down vote










            up vote
            12
            down vote









            I just want to point out, with regards to your second question, that the fact that the $mathbb P^1$ is not equivalent to a simplicial complex homotopic to the sphere built out of affine spaces (or whichever model for an un-Tate-twisted sphere) is exactly what you would expect from Grothendieck et. al.'s theory of motives.



            In fact having a homology or cohomology theory without a notion of Tate twist would be very strong evidence that we are on the wrong track!



            More carefully one might point out that we want a map to etale cohomology and a notion of Chern class, which requires the Tate twisting because Tate twists show up in the Chern class map in etale cohomology.






            share|cite|improve this answer












            I just want to point out, with regards to your second question, that the fact that the $mathbb P^1$ is not equivalent to a simplicial complex homotopic to the sphere built out of affine spaces (or whichever model for an un-Tate-twisted sphere) is exactly what you would expect from Grothendieck et. al.'s theory of motives.



            In fact having a homology or cohomology theory without a notion of Tate twist would be very strong evidence that we are on the wrong track!



            More carefully one might point out that we want a map to etale cohomology and a notion of Chern class, which requires the Tate twisting because Tate twists show up in the Chern class map in etale cohomology.







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered 11 hours ago









            Will Sawin

            65.9k6132275




            65.9k6132275








            • 1




              Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
              – Denis Nardin
              5 hours ago














            • 1




              Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
              – Denis Nardin
              5 hours ago








            1




            1




            Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
            – Denis Nardin
            5 hours ago




            Indeed, the reason why we invert $mathbb{G}_m$ and not just $S^1$ is precisely to capture this kind of phenomena. That it results in a very rich theory is just icing on the cake
            – Denis Nardin
            5 hours ago










            Patriot is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










             

            draft saved


            draft discarded


















            Patriot is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.













            Patriot is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












            Patriot is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.















             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f315816%2fwhy-is-voevodskys-motivic-homotopy-theory-the-right-approach%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Contact image not getting when fetch all contact list from iPhone by CNContact

            count number of partitions of a set with n elements into k subsets

            A CLEAN and SIMPLE way to add appendices to Table of Contents and bookmarks